Solution:
You needn't translate this to symbols to do this problem, but let me do so
to clarify the reasoning. First, let be the statement ``it rains'',
be ``I will wear a coat'', and
be ``I'll stay home''. Thus, the
negation of the statement is
When it rains, I won't wear a coat and I won't stay home.or perhaps you might say
I will go out in the rain without a coat.
Solution:
This is of the form
, which is negated as
,
so we get
This function is invertible or it is continuous.I suppose if you wanted to write this as an implication, you could write
If this function has no inverse, then it is continuous.which is equivalent.
Solution:
Here we have a statement of the form ; the negation of such a
statement is of the form
. Thus, we get
There is a triangle where the sum of the measure of its angles is at least.
Solution:
This statement is nearly already in symbolic form. The negation is
You may recall from calculus that the original statement is the definition
of ``The function is continuous at the point
'', so the latter is
``
is not continous at
''.
There is an implied quantifier on the in the statement, that is, it
really should say
Solution: The negation is clearly
Not every natural number has a unique additive inverse.or
There is a natural number which does not have a unique additive inverse.
But we can elaborate further. If a number does not have a unique
inverse, either it doesn't have an inverse at all, or it has more than
one.2
So, we have
There is a natural number which has no additive inverse, or there is a natural number with more than one additive inverse.
Solution:
This is false. Consider and
. Then
, which is positive,
but
, which is not negative.
Since we are insisting that everything be proven with reference to axioms,
we probably should work a little harder to fully justify all of our
statements. (On an exam, I probably would give nearly full credit for the
above counterexample alone. But this isn't an exam, so I should be complete.)
First we know that and
exist, as consequences of axioms V.8 and V.9,
and the fact that
follows immediately from axiom V.8. But, we have not
shown that
is positive, nor have we shown that
.
One way to see that is to use axiom VI.1 (
), but
perhaps this is a bit of a cheat, because we didn't define ``positive'' in
that way.
So let's prove by contradiction.
Suppose not. Then either or
. But
contradicts
axiom V.12.
If , then
(see the Lemma below). Then applying axiom V.12
(with
,
, and
), we get
. But this
says
, contradicting the earlier statement. Hence,
, that is,
is a positive number.
To see that , let's suppose that there is number
which is the
additive inverse of
. Then
by axiom V.10, and
by
axiom V.8 (and V.5). Thus,
, so
is its own additive inverse.
Finally, we need the following.
Lemma. For all
,
.
Proof. Suppose . Then by axiom V.16,
, and
applying axiom V.8 to the right and V.10 to the left, we get
.
Similarly, if , we have
, so
.
Whew! More than I bargained for here.
Solution:
True. Since we need merely demonstrate existence of such and
, let
and
. Then
is positive (we just did this), and
is negative (again, see the previous part.)
Solution:
This is true. We must show that given a specific integer , we can find
an integer
that meets our needs. Let's break the problem up into three
possibilities:
,
, and
.
Case I: . Let
. First, notice that
, since
and so by axiom V.16,
. By transitivity of
(axiom V.14), we have
. Thus, again by V.16,
. Thus (by transitivity again)
, so
is
positive.
We also need show that is negative. Note that
(distributive law, commutivity), and so
. (using associativity, additive identity). But
is negative,
from before.
Case II: . Now let
. Then
, and
is
positive. To see that
, we have
. Using the fact that
and
, together with
transitivity and axioms V.14 and V.16, we get
.
Case III: . Easiest of all. Let
, so
,
which is positive, and
, negative.
Solution:
This is false. This says that we can find this , and write it
down somewhere. Now for this
and any possible
,
must be
positive and
negative. What about the choice
? It is
supposed to be positive, but
, which isn't positive.
Another way to see this is to write it in symbols. This statement is
But this follows from the previous part. Since the negation is true, the statement can't be.
Solution: Axiom K1 says
For every person, either the person is male or female, but that person cannot be both male and female.This is better said as
Every person is either male or female, but not both.
Solution:
For every personThis is a very stilted way to say, there is a unique person
and a unique person
so that
and
are parents of
,
is male, and
is female.
Everybody has exactly one father and exactly one mother.provided that we know that ``father'' means ``male parent'' and ``mother'' means ``female parent''.
Solution:
means
sinceis a grandfather of
![]()
Solution:
Everybody has a grandfather.
Solution:
Let be an arbitrary person. Then by axiom
,
has a father,
that is, there is some
for which
and
.
Now apply axiom
again to this new
to get
's father, who we
shall denote
. Since
's father's father is his/her grandfather,
we have
. (Of course, there is also the maternal grandfater).
We have shown that for this
,
.
Since
was arbitrary, we apply UG to conclude that
.
Solution:
We want to establish that
, where
is
the statement ``
is divisible by
. Using induction as
suggested, we first check
:
Is divisible by
? Since
, yes it is.
Now we show that
, that is, we want to show
is divisible by
if we know that
is.
If is divisible by 3, then there is an
so that
.
Consequently,
. So, we have